diff options
author | Balagopal Komarath <baluks@gmail.com> | 2024-05-13 11:44:59 +0530 |
---|---|---|
committer | GitHub <noreply@github.com> | 2024-05-13 00:14:59 -0600 |
commit | 7b4a50ac46346fb794c25ca9b4097ad7d39822b6 (patch) | |
tree | 7c9e82e027ea96e5531044cdf8ef333bd2ad6710 /lean4.html.markdown | |
parent | 2c2e8650d9b7b3caba65fa9e3ca6bc55ea08c317 (diff) |
[lean4/en] Documentation for Lean 4 (#4893)
Diffstat (limited to 'lean4.html.markdown')
-rw-r--r-- | lean4.html.markdown | 519 |
1 files changed, 519 insertions, 0 deletions
diff --git a/lean4.html.markdown b/lean4.html.markdown new file mode 100644 index 00000000..4d427cec --- /dev/null +++ b/lean4.html.markdown @@ -0,0 +1,519 @@ +--- +language: "Lean 4" +filename: learnlean4.lean +contributors: + - ["Balagopal Komarath", "https://bkomarath.rbgo.in/"] + - ["Ferinko", "https://github.com/Ferinko"] +--- + +[Lean 4](https://lean-lang.org/) is a dependently typed functional programming +language and an interactive theorem prover. + +```lean4 +/- +An enumerated data type. +-/ +inductive Grade where + | A : Grade + | B : Grade + | F : Grade +deriving Repr + +/- +Functions. +-/ +def grade (m : Nat) : Grade := + if 80 <= m then Grade.A + else if 60 <= m then Grade.B + else Grade.F + +def highMarks := 80 + 9 +def lowMarks := 25 + 25 +#eval grade highMarks +#eval grade lowMarks + +#check (0 : Nat) +/- #check (0 : Grade) -/ /- This is an error. -/ + +/- +Types themselves are values. +-/ +#check (Nat : Type) + +/- +Mathematical propositions are values in Lean. `Prop` is the type of +propositions. + +Here are some simple propositions. +-/ + +#check 0 = 1 +#check 1 = 1 +#check 2^9 - 2^8 = 2^8 + +/- +Notice Lean displays `0 = 1 : Prop` to say: + + The statement "0 = 1" is a proposition. + +We want to distinguish true propositions and false propositions. We do this via +proofs. + +Each proposition is a type. `0 = 1` is a type, `1 = 1` is another type. + +A proposition is true iff there is a value of that type. + +How do we construct a value of type `1 = 1`? We use a constructor that is +defined for that type. + + `Eq.refl a` constructs a value of type `a = a`. (reflexivity) + +Using this we can prove `1 = 1` as follows. +-/ + +theorem one_eq_one : 1 = 1 := Eq.refl 1 + +/- +But there is no way to prove (construct a value of type) `0 = 1`. + +The following will fail. As will `Eq.refl 1` +-/ + +/- theorem zero_eq_one : 0 = 1 := Eq.refl 0 -/ + +/- +Let us prove an inequality involving variables. + +The `calc` primitive allows us to prove equalities using stepwise +calculations. Each step has to be justified by a proof. +-/ +theorem plus_squared (a b : Nat) : (a+b)^2 = a^2 + 2*a*b + b^2 := + calc + (a+b)^2 = (a+b)*(a+b) := Nat.pow_two _ + _ = (a+b)*a + (a+b)*b := Nat.mul_add _ _ _ + _ = a*a + b*a + (a*b + b*b) := by repeat rw [Nat.add_mul] + _ = a*a + b*a + a*b + b*b := by rw [← Nat.add_assoc] + _ = a*a + a*b + a*b + b*b := by rw [Nat.mul_comm b _] + _ = a^2 + a*b + a*b + b*b := by rw [← Nat.pow_two _] + _ = a^2 + a*b + a*b + b^2 := by rw [← Nat.pow_two _] + _ = a^2 + (a*b + a*b) + b^2 := by rw [Nat.add_assoc (a^_)] + _ = a^2 + 2*(a*b) + b^2 := by rw [← Nat.two_mul _] + _ = a^2 + 2*a*b + b^2 := by rw [Nat.mul_assoc _ _ _] +/- +Underscores can be used when there is no ambiguity in what is to be matched. + +For example, in the first step, we want to apply `Nat.pow_two (a+b)`. But, +`(a+b)` is the only pattern here to apply `Nat.pow_two`. So we can omit it. +-/ + +/- +Let us now prove more "realistic" theorems. Those involving logical connectives. + +First, we define even and odd numbers. +-/ +def Even (n : Nat) := ∃ k, n = 2*k +def Odd (n : Nat) := ∃ k, n = 2*k + 1 + +/- +To prove an existential, we can provide specific values if we know them. +-/ +theorem zero_even : Even 0 := + have h : 0 = 2 * 0 := Eq.symm (Nat.mul_zero 2) + Exists.intro 0 h +/- +`Exists.intro v h` proves `∃ x, p x` by substituting `x` by `v` and using the +proof `h` for `p v`. +-/ + +/- +Now, we will see how to use hypothesis that are existentials to prove +conclusions that are existentials. + +The curly braces around parameters `n` and `m` indicate that they are +implicit. Here, Lean will infer them from `hn` and `hm`. +-/ +theorem even_mul_even_is_even' {n m : Nat} (hn : Even n) (hm : Even m) : Even (n*m) := + Exists.elim hn (fun k1 hk1 => + Exists.elim hm (fun k2 hk2 => + Exists.intro (k1 * ( 2 * k2)) ( + calc + n*m = (2 * k1) * (2 * k2) := by rw [hk1, hk2] + _ = 2 * (k1 * (2 * k2)) := by rw [Nat.mul_assoc] + ) + ) + ) + +/- +Most proofs are written using *tactics*. These are commands to Lean that guide +it to construct proofs by itself. + +The same theorem, proved using tactics. +-/ +theorem even_mul_even_is_even {n m : Nat} (hn : Even n) (hm : Even m) : Even (n*m) := by + have ⟨k1, hk1⟩ := hn + have ⟨k2, hk2⟩ := hm + apply Exists.intro $ k1 * (2 * k2) + calc + n*m = (2 * k1) * (2 * k2) := by rw [hk1, hk2] + _ = 2 * (k1 * (2 * k2)) := by rw [Nat.mul_assoc] + +/- +Let us work with implications. +-/ +theorem succ_of_even_is_odd' {n : Nat} : Even n → Odd (n+1) := + fun hn => + have ⟨k, hk⟩ := hn + Exists.intro k ( + calc + n + 1 = 2 * k + 1 := by rw [hk] + ) +/- +To prove an implication `p → q`, you have to write a function that takes a proof +of `p` and construct a proof of `q`. + +Here, `pn` is proof of `Even n := ∃ k, n = 2 *k`. Eliminating the existential +gets us `k` and a proof `hk` of `n = 2 * k`. + +Now, we have to introduce the existential `∃ k, n + 1 = 2 * k + 1`. This `k` is +the same as `k` for `n`. And, the equation is proved by a simple calculation +that substitutes `2 * k` for `n`, which is allowed by `hk`. +-/ + +/- +Same theorem, now using tactics. +-/ +theorem succ_of_even_is_odd {n : Nat} : Even n → Odd (n+1) := by + intro hn + have ⟨k, hk⟩ := hn + apply Exists.intro k + rw [hk] + +/- +The following theorem can be proved similarly. + +We will use this theorem later. + +A `sorry` proves any theorem. It should not be used in real proofs. +-/ +theorem succ_of_odd_is_even {n : Nat} : Odd n → Even (n+1) := sorry + +/- +We can use theorems by applying them. +-/ +example : Odd 1 := by + apply succ_of_even_is_odd + exact zero_even +/- +The two new tactics are: + + - `apply p` where `p` is an implication `q → r` and `r` is the goal rewrites + the goal to `q`. More generally, `apply t` will unify the current goal with + the conclusion of `t` and generate goals for each hypothesis of `t`. + - `exact h` solves the goal by stating that the goal is the same as `h`. +-/ + +/- +Let us see examples of disjunctions. +-/ +example : Even 0 ∨ Odd 0 := Or.inl zero_even +example : Even 0 ∨ Odd 1 := Or.inl zero_even +example : Odd 1 ∨ Even 0 := Or.inr zero_even +/- +Here, we always know from `p ∨ q` which of `p` and/or `q` is correct. So we can +introduce a proof of the correct side. +-/ + +/- +Let us see a more "standard" disjunction. + +Here, from the hypothesis that `n : Nat`, we cannot determine whether `n` is +even or odd. So we cannot construct `Or` directly. + +But, for any specific `n`, we will know which one to construct. + +This is exactly what induction allows us to do. We introduce the `induction` +tactic. + +The inductive hypothesis is a disjunction. When disjunctions appear at the +hypothesis, we use *proof by exhaustive cases*. This is done using the `cases` +tactic. +-/ +theorem even_or_odd {n : Nat} : Even n ∨ Odd n := by + induction n + case zero => left ; exact zero_even + case succ n ihn => + cases ihn with + | inl h => right ; apply (succ_of_even_is_odd h) + | inr h => left ; apply (succ_of_odd_is_even h) +/- +`induction` is not just for natural numbers. It is for any type, since all types +in Lean are inductive. +-/ + +/- +We now state Collatz conjecture. The proof is left as an exercise to the reader. +-/ +def collatz_next (n : Nat) : Nat := + if n % 2 = 0 then n / 2 else 3 * n + 1 + +def iter (k : Nat) (f: Nat → Nat) := + match k with + | Nat.zero => fun x => x + | Nat.succ k' => fun x => f (iter k' f x) + +theorem collatz : ∀ n, n > 0 → ∃ k, iter k collatz_next n = 1 := sorry + +/- +Now, some "corner cases" in logic. +-/ + +/- +The proposition `True` is something that can be trivially proved. + +`True.intro` is a constructor for proving `True`. Notice that it needs no +inputs. +-/ +theorem obvious : True := True.intro + +/- +On the other hand, there is no constructor for `False`. + +We have to use `sorry`. +-/ +theorem impossible : False := sorry + +/- +Any `False` in the hypothesis allows us to conclude anything. + +Written in term style, we use the eliminator `False.elim`. It takes a proof of +`False`, here `h`, and concludes whatever is the goal. +-/ +theorem nonsense (h : False) : 0 = 1 := False.elim h + +/- +The `contradiction` tactic uses any `False` in the hypothesis to conclude the +goal. +-/ +theorem more_nonsense (h : False) : 1 = 2 := by contradiction + +/- +To illustrate constructive vs classical logic, we now prove the contrapositive +theorem. + +The forward direction does not require classical logic. +-/ +theorem contrapositive_forward' (p q : Prop) : (p → q) → (¬q → ¬p) := + fun pq => fun hqf => fun hp => hqf (pq hp) +/- +Use the definition `¬q := q → False`. Notice that we have to construct `p → +False` given `p → q` and `q → False`. This is just function composition. +-/ + +/- +The above proof, using tactics. +-/ +theorem contrapositive_forward (p q : Prop) : (p → q) → (¬q → ¬p) := by + intro hpq + intro + intro hp + specialize hpq hp + contradiction + +/- +The reverse requires classical logic. + +Here, we are required to construct a `q` given values of following types: + + - `(q → False) → (p → False)`. + - `p`. + +This is impossible without using the law of excluded middle. +-/ +theorem contrapositive_reverse' (p q : Prop) : (¬q → ¬p) → (p → q) := + fun hnqnp => + Classical.byCases + (fun hq => fun _ => hq) + (fun hnq => fun hp => absurd hp (hnqnp hnq)) +/- +Law of excluded middle tells us that we will have a `q` or a `q → False`. In the +first case, it is trivial to construct a `q`, we already have it. In the second +case, we give the `q → False` to obtain a `p → False`. Then, we use the fact +(in constructive logic) that given `p` and `p → False`, we can construct +`False`. Once, we have `False`, we can construct anything, and specifically `q`. +-/ + +/- +Same proof, using tactics. +-/ +theorem contrapositive_reverse (p q : Prop) : (¬q → ¬p) → (p → q) := by + intro hnqnp + intro hp + have emq := Classical.em q + cases emq + case inl _ => assumption + case inr h => specialize hnqnp h ; contradiction + +/- +To illustrate how we can define an work with axiomatic systems. Here is a +definition of Groups and some proofs directly translated from "Topics in +Algebra" by Herstein, Second edition. +-/ + +/- +A `section` introduces a namespace. +-/ +section GroupTheory +/- +To define abstract objects like groups, we may use `class`. +-/ +class Group (G : Type u) where + op : G → G → G + assoc : ∀ a b c : G, op (op a b) c = op a (op b c) + e : G + identity: ∀ a : G, op a e = a ∧ op e a = a + inverse: ∀ a : G, ∃ b : G, op a b = e ∧ op b a = e + +/- +Let us introduce some notation to make this convenient. +-/ +open Group +infixl:70 " * " => op + +/- +`G` will always stand for a group and variables `a b c` will be elements of that +group in this `section`. +-/ +variable [Group G] {a b c : G} + +def is_identity (e' : G) := ∀ a : G, (a * e' = a ∧ e' * a = a) + +/- +We prove that the identity element is unique. +-/ +theorem identity_element_unique : ∀ e' : G, is_identity e' → e' = e := by + intro e' + intro h + specialize h e + have ⟨h1, _⟩ := h + have h' := identity e' + have ⟨_, h2⟩ := h' + exact Eq.trans (Eq.symm h2) h1 +/- +Note that we used the `identity` axiom. +-/ + +/- +Left cancellation. We have to use both `identity` and `inverse` axioms from +`Group`. +-/ +theorem left_cancellation : ∀ x y : G, a * x = a * y → x = y := by + have h1 := inverse a + have ⟨ai, a_inv⟩ := h1 + have ⟨_, h2⟩ := a_inv + intro x y + intro h3 + calc + x = (e : G) * x := Eq.symm (identity x).right + _ = ai * a * x := by rw [h2] + _ = ai * (a * x) := by rw [assoc] + _ = ai * (a * y) := by rw [h3] + _ = ai * a * y := by rw [← assoc] + _ = (e : G) * y := by rw [h2] + _ = y := (identity y).right + +end GroupTheory /- Variables `G`, `a`, `b`, `c` are now not in scope. -/ + +/- +Let us see a mutually recursive definition. + +The game of Nim with two heaps. +-/ +abbrev between (lower what upper : Nat) : Prop := lower ≤ what ∧ what ≤ upper + +mutual + def Alice : Nat → Nat → Prop + | n1, n2 => + ∃ k, (between 1 k n1 ∧ (between 1 k n1 → Bob (n1-k) n2)) + ∨ (between 1 k n2 ∧ (between 1 k n2 → Bob n1 (n2-k))) + + def Bob : Nat → Nat → Prop + | n1, n2 => + ∀ k, (between 1 k n1 → Alice (n1-k) n2) + ∧ (between 1 k n2 → Alice n1 (n2-k)) +end + +example : Bob 0 0 := by + intro k + induction k + case zero => + constructor + intro ; contradiction + intro ; contradiction + case succ => + constructor + intro a ; have := a.right ; contradiction + intro a ; have := a.right ; contradiction + +/- +We have to convince Lean of termination when a function is defined using just a +`def`. Here's a simple primality checking algorithm that tests all candidate +divisors. +-/ +def prime' (n : Nat) : Bool := + if h : n < 2 then + false + else + @go 2 n (by omega) +where + go (d : Nat) (n : Nat) {_ : n ≥ d} : Bool := + if h : n = d then /- `h` needed for `omega` below. -/ + true + else if n % d = 0 then + false + else + @go (Nat.succ d) n (by omega) + termination_by (n - d) +/- +We have to specify that the recursive function `go` terminates because `n-k` +decreases in each recursive call. This needs the hypothesis `n > k` at the +recursive call site. But the function itself can only assume that `n ≥ k`. We +label the test `n ≤ k` by `h` so that the falsification of this proposition can +be used by `omega` later to conclude that `n > k`. + +The tactic `omega` can solve simple equalities and inequalities. +-/ +/- +You can also instruct Lean to not check for totality by prefixing `partial` to +`def`. +-/ + +/- +Or, we can rewrite the function to test the divisors from largest to +smallest. In this case, Lean easily verifies that the function is total. +-/ +def prime (n : Nat) : Bool := + if n < 2 then + true + else + go (n-1) n +where + go d n := + if d < 2 then + true + else if n % d = 0 then + false + else + go (d-1) n +/- +Now, to Lean, it is obvious that `go` will terminate because `d` decreases in +each recursive call. +-/ +#eval prime 57 +#eval prime 97 +``` + +For further learning, see: + +* [Functional Programming in Lean](https://lean-lang.org/functional_programming_in_lean/) +* [Theorem Proving in Lean 4](https://lean-lang.org/theorem_proving_in_lean4/) +* [Lean 4 Manual](https://lean-lang.org/lean4/doc/) |